Thomas Kuhn's Theory of Scientific Revolutions


Natural Phenomena, Science, and Philosophy of Science
Kuhn's Model of Scientific Revolutions
Some Philosophical Aspects of Kuhn's Theory
Questions for Study

Natural Phenomena, Science, and Philosophy of Science

Now that we have looked at what is often referred to as the first major scientific revolution in modern history -- the cosmological revolution from Copernicus to Newton -- we will go on to look at philosophies of science that attempt to explain the historical dynamics of scientific revolutions. The process can be conceptualized, in a preliminary and somewhat simplistic way, as a three tiered one:

Kuhn's Model of Scientific Revolutions

Perhaps the best known philosopher of science in the last half century is Thomas Kuhn (1922-1996), who was for many years a professor of philosophy and history of science at MIT. Kuhn, who died just a few years ago, held his PhD in physics, but was asked as a young faculty member to teach a course in history of science. He became fascinated with the process by which theories, once held to be true, were replaced by very different ones, also held to be true. For example, the view that all matter was made of Earth, Air, Water and Fire held sway for over two millenia; yet it now seems crude and even child-like in comparison to the modern theory of chemical elements. Nonetheless, it was held to be adequate for a much longer period of time.

For Kuhn, the problem was two-fold: (i) to explain why scientific theories are accepted, and (ii) to explain why scientific theories are replaced. These two aspects are intimately related, and the key concept that Kuhn develops is that of "paradigm" -- a reigning or dominant approach to solving problems in a given area of science.

Kuhn presented his views in Structure of Scientific Revolutions (first edition 1962, second edition 1970). He argued that scientific revolutions proceed through the following stages:

  1. "Normal Science", that is to say everyday, bread-and-butter science, is a "puzzle-solving" activity conducted under a reigning "paradigm".

  2. An "anomaly" arises when a puzzle, considered as important or essential in some way, cannot be solved. The anomaly cannot be written off as just an ill-conceived research project; it continues to assert itself as a thorn in the side of the practicing scientists. The anomaly is a novelty that cannot be written off, and which cannot be solved. Examples of anomalies include:

  3. This opens up a period called the "crisis", during which time new methods and approaches are permitted, since the older ones have proved incapable of rising to the task at hand (solving the anomaly). Views and procedures previously considered heretical are temporarily permitted, in the hope of cracking the anomaly.

  4. One of these new approaches is successful, and it becomes the new paradigm through a "paradigm shift". This constitutes the core of the scientific revolution.

  5. The new paradigm is popularized in text-books, which serve as the instruction material for the next generation of scientists, who are brought up with the idea that the paradigm -- once new and revolutionary -- is just the way things are done. The novelty of the scientific revolution recedes and disappears, until the process is begun anew with another anomaly-crisis-paradigm shift.

Some Philosophical Aspects of Kuhn's Theory

Kuhn also has made a number of major philosophical claims in the context of developing his model of how science produces revolutions in theory. I mention them here in passing, as just the critical examination of these claims could be the subject of a whole course:

(1) Scientists cannot by themselves "translate" between and old and a new paradigm; these paradigms are "incommensurable", and can be (partially) translated only with the aid of historians and philosophers of science. For example, the explanation for combustion before the oxygen theory invoked a substance, widely accepted in the 18th century, known as "phlogiston", which was given off when a material burned. The modern theory explains the same phenomena as due to the taking-in of oxygen, not the expulsion of the non-existent "phlogiston". A student of chemistry would need a specialist to translate the older theory into modern terms, and even then, aspects of it would remain somewhat mysterious, since taken out of their 18th century context where they made sense.

(2) Scientists escape the dominant paradigm which forms, as it were, their "skin", inside of which they conduct their research. Consequently, there is no "higher authority" who can adjudicate, or decide once and for all, competing truth-claims. All we have are the paradigms of today (the context for on-going research) and those of the past (partially translated by historians and philosophers of science). Not only can there be no absolute truth (true once and for all), but Kuhn makes the more radical claim that the concept of "truth" can be dispensed with entirely, replaced by that of "successful problem solving within a paradigm". Similarly, "objectivity" as a notion independent of the inquiring scientist has no meaning, and is replaced by the methods adopted as standard within the community of scientists.

(3) Kuhn believed, however, that science progresses over time. This is not, however, a question of approaching or achieving "the truth" (see (2) above),. but a matter of solving more problems under the current paradigm than under past ones. (Some old problems drop out as "pseudo-problems" for the new paradigm, but overall, more new problems get solved).

Questions for Study

(1) What does Kuhn mean by a paradigm?
(2) What does Kuhn mean by an anomaly?
(3) What does Kuhn mean by a crisis?
(4) How does Kuhn understand the notion of "scientific revolution"?